FRAL - Franco-allemand en sciences humaines et sociales

Mathematics: Objectivity by representation – MathObRe

Mathematics : Objectivity by Representation

Can the practical turn in philosophy of mathematics produce some progress on the role of representations in mathematical ontology and mathematical reasoning? is the leading questions of this project. <br />Accordingly, we plan to analyse in which sense stipulations determine objects by appealing to appropriate representations, in what sense inferential rigor can depend on these stipulations, and in what sense it is possible to characterize informal provability by formal means.

Representation, object-constitution and reasoning

The aim of our project is to argue for a twofold (hypo)thesis:<br />(a) Mathematical representations established by stipulations contribute to the constitution of mathematical ontology and to shaping of mathematical reasoning.<br />(b) Mathematical object-constitution is analogous to scientific object-constitution.<br />The stakes are at once methodological, as a way of rethinking the foundations of mathematics, and ontological, as it allows to test an intermediate position, between platonism and nominalism, on the one hand (concerning mathematical objects), and between formalism and intuitionism, on the other hand (concerning mathematical reasoning). The arguments we discuss are both historical and systematic.<br />Given how we take mathematical objects to be constituted by stipulations, we should study different cases in which some mathematical objects have been historically constituted in this way, that is by isolating some empirical artefacts and taking them as concrete (or empirical) representations of abstract objects that are identified, in turn, by fixing their relations with these representations. Mathematical objects admitting concrete representations, and, a fortiori, those that are identified through them can, in some senses, be said to be real, as opposed to ideal ones, the latter being those that do not admit such representations. <br />Concerning mathematical reasoning, our goal is to clarify two possibilities to interpret the situation: To conceive mathematical reasoning as referring to mathematical representation or to use a new logic with “contentful” inferences, for rendering mathematical reasoning. <br />Once obtained a solution of this problem, our research will be devoted to a comparison between well-known logical reconstructions of theoretical terms and entities in the philosophy of science with the logical reconstruction of mathematical terms and entities in the foundations of mathematics.

The methodology of our research will combine abstract philosophical considerations with logical analysis. Still, historical inquiries (based on the analysis of texts and mutual influences), and attention to mathematical practice as such will also be exploited. This is why we include in the project mathematicians and historians of mathematics. We also asked for the collaboration of some internationally recognized specialists from France and Germany who do not belong to the three institutional partners, and appeal to other colleagues we are used to collaborate with, coming from abroad.
The sustained thesis seems, so to say, the limit to which converge the classical philosophical positions with regard to foundations of mathematics: The three main initiators of this project, initially engaged in pragmatic (Heinzmann), formalist (Leitgeb) and Platonistic (Panza) traditions, came to elaborate and share a common position facing to the difficulties of their original approaches. This is the main reason for the French-German collaboration. Its synergy should allow a better elaboration of this common position on the basis of the different starting points.

On the French side, the project is directly connected with M. Detlefsen’s chaire d’excellence “Ideal of Proofs” (ANR, 2007-2011; www.univ-nancy2.fr/poincare/idealsofproof/) directed by J.J. Szczeciniarz, G. Heinzmann and M. Panza, the latter two being involved in the present project. Our aim is to develop the research pursued in this project in a different direction: instead of focusing on “ideal elements” involved in mathematical theories and proofs, we focus on the role of representation, especially if provided by an affinity to empirical artefacts.
On the German side, the project is triggered by two streams of research that have emerged at the MCMP within the last two years: i) The study of ante rem structuralism in the philosophy of mathematics (the view that mathematics concerns structures, which are only determined up to isomorphism); ii) the questions whether logical concepts are constituted by logical rules, and theoretical concepts are determined by scientific theories.
In the last decades, many studies have aimed to overcome classical positions in mathematical ontology and epistemology as Platonism, nominalism, and classical pragmatism (as presented in Kitcher 1984). These efforts suggest looking at mathematical practice as a source for finding a solution to the problem these positions were willing to answer. This is today a crucial task for philosophy of mathematics, and for example witnessed by the activities and publications of the Association for the Philosophy of Mathematical Practice (http://institucional.us.es/apmp/index_members.htm), which counts as its members many participants to our project.
Even taken together, all these studies and events give no answer to our focal concern: clarifying the role of representations in mathematical reasoning and proofs and the way they contribute to mathematical ontology and understanding. We believe therefore, that our project could add important insights to the understanding of mathematical practice.

The outstanding features of our aims in the four scientific tasks (task (2) to (5)) are the following:
(a) Representational Identification
Parsons (2008) mentions, as examples of mathematical quasi-empirical objects, geometrical figures of Euclid’s plane geometry, natural numbers conceived as strings of strokes, and finite small sets. However, he only considers the second example. This suggests of developing other examples of representational identification This is the main feature of task (2).
(b) Varieties of Representational Identification
This task (3) has a comparative and specifically philosophical nature. Its basic feature is that of reflecting on the general notion of representational identification in its relations with the notion of intuition, and of comparing different varieties of representational identification of mathematical objects.
(c) What’s an informal proof?
Task (4) aims to investigate the relation between pragmatism and the practical turn by focusing on the concept of informal proof and aesthetic elements (in Goodman’s sense) in mathematical proof. Our main feature is to give some criteria, improved by mathematical practice, in order to decide which of different proofs of a theorem is more explanatory then an other.
(d) Theoretical terms and entities vs mathematical terms and entities
The main feature of task (5) is to investigated the thesis that mathematical objects would be determined by mathematical terms and theories in much the same way in which theoretical objects are determined by theoretical terms and theories according to Carnap’s analysis. Mathematical representation would thus end up prior to the ontology of mathematics.

Heinzmann, G. (1999), “Poincaré on Understanding Mathematics”, Philosophia Scientiae 3 (2), 43-60.
Heinzmann, G. (2013), L’intuition épistémique. Une approche pragmatique du contexte de justification en mathématiques et en philosophie, Paris : Vrin (Mathesis).
Heinzmann, G. (2015), Pragmatism and the Practical Turn in Philosophy of Mathematics: Explanatory Proofs, in : E. Agazzi, G. Heinzmann (eds), Pragmatism and the Practical Turn in Philosophy of Sciences. Milan : Franco Angeli Editore (in press).
Jullien, C. (2008), Mathématiques et esthétique – Une Exploration goodmanienne, Presses universitaires de Rennes, coll. Aesthetica, 2008.
Leitgeb, H. and J. Jadyman (2008), “Criteria of Identity and Structuralist Ontology”, Philosophia Mathematica 16/3, 2008, 388-396.
Leitgeb, H. (2009), “On Formal and Informal Provability”, in: O. Linnebo and O. Bueno (eds.), New Waves in Philosophy of Mathematics, Palgrave Macmillan, New York, 2009, pp. 263-299.
Leitgeb, H. (2011), “New Life for Carnap's Aufbau?”, Synthese 180/2, 2011, 265-299.
Panza, M. (2011a) “Rethinking Geometrical Exactness”, Historia Mathematica, 38, 1, 2011, pp. 42-95.
Panza, M. (2011b) “The Twofold Role of Diagrams in Euclid’s Plane Geometry”, Synthese, 186, n° 1, 2012, pp. 55-102.
Panza, M.& Sereni, A. (2013), Plato’s Problem, Palgrave, Basingstoke, 2013.
Rebuschi, M. (2006). “IF & Epistemic Action Logic”. In J. van Benthem et al. (eds.): The Age of Alternative Logics. Assessing Philosophy of Logic and Mathematics Today, Dordrecht, Springer, 261-281.
Sinaceur, H.B. (2008), Richard Dedekind: La création des nombres, Vrin, Paris, 2008.
Steinberger, F. (2013), «On the Equivalence Conjecture for Proof-Theoretic Harmony«, Notre Dame Journal for Formal Logic 54 (1), 79-86.
Wagner P. (2012), ed. Carnap’s Ideal of Explication and Naturalism, Basingstoke, Palgrave Macmillan.

As far the physical world is concerned, the standard realist attitude which conceives of objects as existing independently of our representations of them might be (prima facie) plausible: if things go well, we represent physical objects in the way we do because they are so-and-so. In contrast, as we want to argue, in the mathematical world the situation is reversed: if things go well, mathematical objects are so-and-so because we represent them as we do. This does not mean that mathematics could not be objective: mathematical representations might be subject to constraints that impose objectivity on what they constitute. If this is right, in order to understand the nature of mathematical objects we should first understand how mathematical representations work. In the words of Kreisel’s famous dictum: “the problem is not the existence of mathematical objects but the objectivity of mathematical statements” (Dummett 1978, p. xxxviii).
The problem we tackle concerns the philosophical question of clarifying the role of representations in mathematical reasoning and proofs and the way they contribute to mathematical ontology and understanding. This is a fresh inquiry concerning a classical problem in philosophy of mathematics connecting understanding to proofs and to the way the ontology of mathematic is conceived. But our starting point is neither classical proof theory nor classical metaphysics. We are rather looking at the problem by opening the door to the practical turn in science.
In our perspective the question is then neither to find a topic-neutral formalization of mathematical reasoning, nor to offer a new argument for the existence of mathematical objects. We rather wonder how appropriate domains of mathematical (abstract) objects are constituted, by appealing to different sorts of representations, and how appropriate reasoning on them are licensed.
Accordingly, we plan to analyse:
(i) in which sense in mathematical practice relevant stipulations determine objects by appealing to appropriate representations;
(ii) in what sense inferential rigor conceived in a contentual (informal) perspective can depend on these stipulations;
(iii) in what sense it is possible to characterize nevertheless (by interlinking philosophical studies with scientific investigations) informal provability by formal means, which allows using logic and mathematics as a tool for epistemology.
We also contrast our approach with classical foundational approaches of mathematics and logic, like classical Platonism and Nominalism, which both share an “existential attitude” facing mathematical objects (they both take as crucial the question whether they exist or do not exist, though giving opposite answers) and consider mathematical reasoning as topic-invariant.


Project coordination

Gerhard HEINZMANN (Laboratoire d'Histoire des Sciences et de Philosophie — Archives Henri-Poncaré) – gerhard.heinzmann@univ-lorraine.fr

The author of this summary is the project coordinator, who is responsible for the content of this summary. The ANR declines any responsibility as for its contents.

Partner

IHPST Institut d'Histoire et de Philosophie des Sciences et des Techniques
IECN Institut Elie Cartan de Lorraine
MCMP Munich Center of Mathematical Philosophy
IHPST / CNRS IHPST
LHSP-AP Laboratoire d'Histoire des Sciences et de Philosophie — Archives Henri-Poncaré

Help of the ANR 182,023 euros
Beginning and duration of the scientific project: February 2014 - 36 Months

Useful links

Explorez notre base de projets financés

 

 

ANR makes available its datasets on funded projects, click here to find more.

Sign up for the latest news:
Subscribe to our newsletter